Philosophy often serves as a guide for those seeking to live more meaningful lives, yet many may not fully grasp the importance of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s concept of “meaning as use.” This central idea plays a crucial role in his philosophy and can profoundly impact how we apply philosophical insights to enrich our lives. Understanding this concept is essential for appreciating its significance and harnessing its potential in our personal pursuit of meaning. This article examines Wittgenstein’s philosophy, the principle of meaning as use, and their connection to living a more meaningful and thoughtful life.
Key features of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s philosophy
Ludwig Wittgenstein was a 20th-century philosopher known for his profound contributions to the philosophy of language, logic, and mind. His work is often divided into two key phases. The first is represented by his early masterpiece, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, which focused on the relationship between language and reality. Wittgenstein argued that language works like a picture, with sentences representing facts about the world. He believed that what can be said clearly should be said, and what cannot be expressed in language—such as ethics or the mystical—should remain silent.
The second phase of his philosophy is captured in Philosophical Investigations, where he shifted his focus to how language is used in everyday life. Wittgenstein introduced the idea of language games, suggesting that the meaning of words depends on their use within specific contexts. He emphasized that language is not rigid but fluid, shaped by cultural practices and human interactions.


At the heart of Wittgenstein’s philosophy is the idea that many philosophical problems arise from misunderstandings of language. By analyzing how we use words, he believed such problems could be dissolved rather than solved. His work remains influential across disciplines, inspiring debates in philosophy, linguistics, psychology, and beyond. Through his explorations, Wittgenstein transformed how we think about language, meaning, and the nature of understanding.
What is meaning as use?
Ludwig Wittgenstein’s view about meaning as use is central to his later philosophy, particularly in his work Philosophical Investigations. He argued that the meaning of a word is not tied to some fixed essence or definition but is instead found in how the word is used in language. According to Wittgenstein, language is a dynamic activity, and words have meaning through their role in what he called “language games.” These language games are varied contexts or activities where words gain their significance based on how they are applied by people in those specific situations.
For Wittgenstein, language is not a single, uniform system but a collection of practices or activities, each with its own internal rules and purposes. A word’s meaning emerges from its function within these practices, and there is no universal, overarching rule that determines meaning in every situation. This perspective emphasizes the practical and context-dependent nature of language. Meaning is not an inherent property of words but is shaped by their use within the framework of social interaction and communication.
By shifting the focus to usage, Wittgenstein moved away from earlier philosophical ideas that treated meaning as a fixed relationship between words and objects. Instead, he highlighted the fluid and adaptable nature of language, which functions as a tool humans use in their everyday lives.
This example clearly demonstrates this philosophical perspective. Imagine a group of people playing a game in which they use coloured tiles. To one group, the tiles act as tokens for trading goods, representing value in a marketplace. To another group, the same tiles are used to build patterns or for artistic expression. The meaning of the tiles changes depending on how they are being used in each situation. For Wittgenstein, this illustrates how the meaning of a word stems from its use in a specific context. The same tile does not inherently carry one fixed meaning; instead, its meaning is shaped by the actions and rules of those interacting with it. Similarly, in language, words are not attached to universal definitions but derive their significance based on how they function within a given setting, as guided by shared human practices and activities.
Challenges to Ludwig Wittgenstein’s view about meaning as use
Philosophers who object to or reject Ludwig Wittgenstein’s view about meaning as use often raise several key issues, focusing on potential limitations and challenges in his approach to language and meaning. One common objection is that the idea of meaning being tied solely to use might not fully account for abstract or theoretical concepts. For instance, many argue that some words or phrases are used in ways disconnected from practical contexts, existing purely in theoretical or imaginative realms. This creates difficulty when trying to explain their meaning strictly in terms of use.
Another criticism is that the concept of use may oversimplify the relationship between language and thought. Critics claim that language is deeply influenced by internal cognitive processes, emotions, and intentions, which may not always be directly observable through how words are used in specific contexts. By focusing heavily on external use, Wittgenstein’s theory might overlook these internal dimensions of meaning, creating an incomplete framework.
Additionally, some philosophers argue that Wittgenstein’s perspective does not adequately address the origins of meaning itself. While “use” may explain how meanings are maintained in language, it does not necessarily clarify how meanings are established in the first place. This gap leads some to believe that his view lacks depth when discussing how we come to understand and define new words, particularly ones that arise outside established linguistic and cultural norms.
A further objection involves the complexity of human communication. Critics point out that many forms of communication involve subtle, layered meanings that go beyond literal use. Factors like metaphor, irony, or poetry involve interpretations that cannot be fully captured by examining usage patterns alone. This complexity suggests that meaning might depend on deeper semantic or contextual principles that Wittgenstein’s view does not sufficiently explore.
Ultimately, while Wittgenstein’s approach has been influential and valuable, critics highlight these limitations as areas where his perspective may fall short in addressing the rich, multifaceted nature of meaning in human language.
Why meaning as use is important to Ludwig Wittgenstein’s philosophy
These are some of the central reasons why grasping the concept of meaning as use is crucial to comprehending Ludwig Wittgenstein’s philosophy.
- Connection Between Language and Life
The idea of meaning as use underscores the deep connection between language and the activities of daily life. Language is not isolated from the world but is embedded in the way people live, work, and interact. The importance of this connection lies in how it shifts focus from abstract definitions of words to their practical application in different contexts. This approach helps in understanding how language functions dynamically, adapting to the needs of people in varied situations. By concentrating on the role language plays in human activities, we can better grasp its purpose and effectiveness.
- Clarity in Communication
Focusing on how words are used rather than what they mean in a theoretical sense can lead to greater clarity in communication. Words gain meaning through shared understanding within specific communities or contexts, which helps people communicate ideas effectively. This perspective is especially important in avoiding misunderstandings, as it emphasizes the context in which words are employed. By appreciating this aspect, we can comprehend how language takes on meaning based on the situation and the shared practices of the individuals using it.
- Framework for Analyzing Language
The concept provides a framework for analyzing how language works in practical terms. Rather than treating language as a fixed system, it allows for exploration of its flexible and evolving nature. This is valuable for studying how language changes over time and how new words or usages emerge in response to societal developments. Understanding meaning as use encourages the observation of everyday interactions, revealing how language evolves to meet changing needs and contexts. It thus highlights the adaptability and richness of language as a tool for human expression.
Contrasting Ludwig Wittgenstein’s philosophy with John Locke’s philosophy
Ludwig Wittgenstein’s idea of “meaning as use,” which suggests that the meaning of a word is found in how it is used in everyday language, offers a key difference from John Locke’s philosophy. Locke, as a classical empiricist, believed that words function as labels for ideas formed in the mind. For Locke, language represents thought, and words correspond to particular ideas or concepts stored internally. This perspective emphasizes a connection between words and the mental representations they signify.
Wittgenstein’s view takes a different path. Instead of defining meaning by its relationship to internal ideas, he focuses on the role language plays within human activity. By saying “meaning is use,” Wittgenstein highlights that the way people use words in their social, cultural, and practical interactions gives them meaning. Language, in this sense, operates as a shared tool, not just a reflection of internal thought.
The key distinction lies in how the two think about the connection between words and meaning. Locke’s approach is rooted in individual cognition, associating language directly with mental ideas, whereas Wittgenstein emphasizes the external, practical context of language use. This moves the discussion from introspection to the public and social realm of language, marking a significant shift in how we understand communication and meaning.
Meaning As Use, Ludwig Wittgenstein’s philosophy and the meaning of life
Reflecting on Ludwig Wittgenstein’s philosophy, particularly the perspective that meaning comes from use, can have a significant impact on how we approach living a more meaningful life. Whether or not you agree with his perspective, exploring his thoughts encourages a deeper awareness of the connection between language and actions in everyday life. Words shape our understanding of the world, and what we say often influences our experiences and relationships. By thinking critically about how we use language, we can better align our words and actions with the type of life we want to live.
For example, taking time to consider how we communicate with others can lead to more thoughtful interactions. If we use kind and intentional language, it fosters stronger relationships and creates a more compassionate environment around us. On the other hand, careless or negative language can unintentionally harm others or even distort how we view ourselves. Reflecting on how we express ourselves helps ensure that what we say supports well-being and growth for everyone involved.
This way of thinking also invites us to examine how meaning shows up in our actions. Life often feels more meaningful when our actions are consistent with our values. For instance, if helping others is important to you, acting on that value—whether through volunteering, supporting a friend, or small acts of kindness—makes life feel richer and more fulfilling. Words and actions together can reinforce the sense of purpose and coherence in how we live.
Ultimately, considering this approach pushes us to ask important questions about what we find meaningful. Are we living with intention? Are our words and actions creating the life we want or adding to the lives of others? These reflections can serve as powerful tools in making changes or adjustments that lead to greater fulfillment. Wittgenstein’s philosophy encourages us to think beyond rigid definitions of meaning and instead focus on how meaning is created and shared every day. Whether or not we accept his view, using this lens to better understand ourselves and our interactions can be a step toward living a life that feels truly significant.
Further reading
Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Clarendon Press.
Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2009). Wittgenstein: Rules, grammar and necessity. Wiley-Blackwell.
Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press.
Diamond, C. (1991). The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy, and the mind. MIT Press.
Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Harvard University Press.
McGinn, M. (2013). Wittgenstein and the philosophical investigations. Routledge.
Rhees, R. (1970). Discussions of Wittgenstein. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Schroeder, S. (2006). Wittgenstein on the foundations of mathematics. Routledge.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The Blue and Brown Books. Harper & Row.