Skip to content
Home » Articles » George Berkeley’s Philosophy and primary and secondary qualities

George Berkeley’s Philosophy and primary and secondary qualities

Download this free Ebook (pdf):

Download free ebooks about the meaning of life, philosophy of life, and current thinkers
More ideas on Instagram / X

Understanding the distinction between primary and secondary qualities is essential when exploring George Berkeley’s philosophy and its impact on the development of a personal philosophy of life. Although this concept is widely recognized, its significance is not always fully appreciated. Properly grasping this idea can greatly influence how we shape and refine our own philosophical outlook. This article examines George Berkeley’s philosophical contributions, the concept of primary and secondary qualities, and their importance in guiding our understanding of life.

Key features of George Berkeley’s philosophy

George Berkeley was an Irish philosopher best known for his theory of immaterialism, also referred to as subjective idealism. At the core of his philosophy is the idea that material objects do not exist independently of our perception. According to Berkeley, the things we see, touch, or feel are only collections of ideas perceived by the mind. For example, a tree exists because someone perceives it; if no one is around to see the tree, it still exists because it is perceived by God, the ultimate observer.

Berkeley challenged the notion of material substances by arguing that our knowledge of the world comes entirely through sensory experience. For him, there is no proof of a material world existing outside our perceptions. Instead, reality consists of minds and the ideas they perceive. He famously summarized this view with the phrase “esse est percipi,” meaning “to be is to be perceived.”

This philosophy also emphasized the role of God as the continuous perceiver of all things, ensuring the consistency and orderliness of the world. Berkeley’s ideas were designed to counter skepticism, as he believed his theory supported a more direct and immediate relationship with the world and God. Although controversial, his philosophy remains a key contribution to the discussion of the nature of reality and perception in modern philosophy.

What is primary and secondary qualities?

George Berkeley, an influential philosopher, is known for his unique ideas about perception and reality. He challenged the distinction between primary and secondary qualities, which was widely accepted by other thinkers of his time. Primary qualities were thought to exist in objects themselves, independent of any observer, while secondary qualities were considered dependent on the observer’s perception. Berkeley rejected this divide, arguing that all qualities we perceive are dependent on the mind and exist only when they are experienced.

For Berkeley, the existence of objects is tied to being perceived. He famously stated, “To be is to be perceived” (esse est percipi). This means that objects, along with their qualities, do not exist independently in the external world but only in the perceptions of observers. According to him, the idea that some qualities could exist outside the mind is contradictory because we can only understand or experience qualities through our perceptions.

By emphasizing this view, Berkeley proposed that reality is fundamentally a mental construct, and everything we perceive exists in our minds or the mind of a higher being, such as God. This perspective challenges the assumption that there is a material world separate from our experiences, placing perception and the mind at the center of our understanding of reality.

This idea can be demonstrated through the following example. Imagine holding an apple in your hand. Its bright red colour and sweet taste are qualities you perceive through your senses. According to Berkeley’s perspective, qualities like colour, texture, and taste exist only in the mind of the individual experiencing them. Now consider the apple’s weight and shape—while they may seem more inherent to the apple itself, Berkeley would argue that these too are experienced through perception. For instance, if a smaller person lifts the apple, they may experience it as heavier than a stronger person would. Both primary qualities, like weight and size, and secondary qualities, like taste and colour, depend entirely on the observer’s perception. Without someone there to perceive it, the apple’s qualities and even its existence in its current form would be in question. This highlights Berkeley’s challenge to the idea of an objective reality.

Challenges to George Berkeley’s view about primary and secondary qualities

Philosophers who object to George Berkeley’s ideas about primary and secondary qualities often do so because they find his arguments overly restrictive or believe they lead to problematic conclusions about the nature of reality. A common objection is that rejecting the distinction between these qualities seems to undermine scientific reasoning. Many philosophers argue that primary qualities, like size, shape, or motion, exist independently of our perception, making them objectively measurable and essential to scientific inquiry. By treating these as dependent on perception, critics worry that Berkeley’s view disrupts the foundation of modern science, which relies on the assumption that the physical world exists independently of human experience.

Another reason philosophers push back against Berkeley’s ideas is that they feel his perspective creates more philosophical problems than it solves. If all qualities of an object are tied to perception, it becomes challenging to explain how and why the physical world seems consistent and predictable. For example, if no one perceives an object, does it cease to exist? Critics argue that this leads to an unstable or incomplete account of reality, where the existence of the external world becomes dependent on the presence of observers, which seems counterintuitive to many.

Practical objections also arise based on different human experiences. Critics point out that perception can vary widely between people. For instance, people might see colours differently due to colour blindness or interpret sounds differently based on hearing ability. If qualities are entirely based on perception, how can we account for the variations in experience? Philosophers argue that this variability suggests the existence of an objective, shared world that goes beyond what we perceive.

These objections highlight a broader philosophical debate around the balance between subjective experience and objective reality. While Berkeley’s ideas are insightful and thought-provoking, many find them too radical, arguing that they fail to adequately address the complexities of how humans engage with and understand the external world.

Why primary and secondary qualities are important to George Berkeley’s philosophy

These are some of the main reasons why grasping the concept of primary and secondary qualities is essential to comprehending George Berkeley’s philosophy.

  1. Clarifies the Nature of Perception

The philosophical distinction between primary and secondary qualities helps explain how we perceive and relate to the world around us. Primary qualities, such as shape, size, and motion, are typically thought to exist independently of an observer, while secondary qualities, like colour, taste, and sound, rely on the observer’s senses to exist. This distinction is important because it highlights how much of our experience of reality is shaped by perception. Understanding this concept is crucial when studying Berkeley’s ideas, as it sets the stage for exploring how human perception plays a role in defining what is real and how we engage with the world. By analyzing the differences between these qualities, one can better grasp the underlying questions about the relationship between the mind and external reality.

  1. Challenges Objectivity in Reality

Dividing qualities into primary and secondary ones inherently raises questions about whether or not anything can truly be objective. Primary qualities are often seen as more “real” because they are thought to exist regardless of whether someone perceives them, whereas secondary qualities depend entirely on human experience. This framework forces philosophers to think deeply about the nature of objects—whether they are as we perceive them or if their existence can be independent of perception. This questioning is vital for understanding Berkeley’s philosophy, as it provides a foundation for a broader discussion about what can be said to truly exist and how perception shapes our understanding of reality. By considering this distinction, students can appreciate the complex interconnections between the mind’s interpretation and the material world’s existence.

Contrasting George Berkeley’s philosophy with Galileo Galilei’s philosophy

George Berkeley and Galileo Galilei had differing views on the nature of primary and secondary qualities, which highlight a major contrast in their philosophies. Galileo proposed that the world could be understood through measurable qualities, such as size, shape, motion, and number—referred to as primary qualities. He believed these qualities existed independently of human perception and were objective aspects of reality. On the other hand, secondary qualities, such as colour, taste, smell, and sound, were seen by Galileo as subjective. He argued that these secondary qualities existed only in the mind of the observer and did not belong to objects themselves.

Berkeley took this distinction in a different direction. While Galileo suggested that primary qualities could exist apart from perception, Berkeley did not agree with this conclusion. Berkeley’s philosophy rejected the idea that anything could exist without being perceived. This led him to challenge the very foundation of Galileo’s argument, asserting that even the so-called primary qualities depended on perception for their existence. For Berkeley, all qualities—whether primary or secondary—were ultimately tied to the observer.

The contrast lies in their underlying assumptions; Galileo emphasized an independent reality governed by mathematical principles, where objective primary qualities served as the foundation of truth. Meanwhile, Berkeley introduced a perception-based approach, implying that understanding reality cannot be detached from the human experience of observing it. This key difference marks a philosophical shift between the two thinkers with regard to how the world is understood and what constitutes reality.

Primary and Secondary Qualities, George Berkeley’s philosophy and the meaning of life

Reflecting on George Berkeley’s view about primary and secondary qualities might seem like a purely academic pursuit, but its relevance goes far beyond theories and philosophy classrooms. At its core, engaging with ideas like these encourages us to question our perceptions of reality and think deeply about how we engage with the world. Whether or not one agrees with Berkeley, taking the time to reflect on such perspectives pushes us to explore what truly matters in life and how we assign meaning to our experiences.

For example, in everyday life, we often take what we see, hear, and feel at face value. But reflecting on ideas like Berkeley’s provides an opportunity to step back and consider how much of what we experience truly defines our reality. This kind of reflection can help us prioritize the aspects of life that bring richness and fulfillment, such as relationships, personal growth, and self-awareness. Instead of focusing solely on external, material aspects of existence, we might shift our attention to intangible but deeply meaningful qualities, such as kindness, love, and creativity.

Additionally, reflecting on philosophical views like Berkeley’s allows us to practice humility and openness. Life can often feel rigid, as though there’s only one way to think, act, or live. Yet, engaging with challenging perspectives reminds us that reality itself can be interpreted in many ways. This kind of mindset can inspire us to approach challenges and interactions with a more open heart and a deeper sense of curiosity. It’s a practice that encourages us to look beyond surface-level assumptions and find deeper meaning in the world around us.

Ultimately, life is about finding purpose and navigating the complexities of being human. Philosophical reflections, such as those inspired by Berkeley, invite us to step outside of the ordinary and grapple with broader questions about existence and meaning. Whether or not we agree with his ideas, such exercises can shape us into more thoughtful, intentional individuals, fully engaged in living a life of depth and authenticity. These reflections can build the foundation for a more meaningful existence, rooted in a genuine understanding of what matters most.

Further reading

Berkeley, G. (1710). A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. Oxford University Press.

Berkeley, G. (1734). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. Hackett Publishing Company.

Bennett, J. (1971). Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central themes. Oxford University Press.

Foster, J. (1982). The case for idealism. Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Gallois, A. (1974). Berkeley and Perceptual Relativity. Philosophical Review, 83(4), 498-510.

Grayling, A. C. (1986). Berkeley: The central arguments. Open Court.

Jolley, N. (1990). The light of the soul: Theories of ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Berkeley. Clarendon Press.

Pappas, G. S. (2000). Berkeley’s thought. Cornell University Press.

Rickless, S. C. (2013). Locke, Berkeley, and the semantics of secondary qualities. Philosophical Review, 122(2), 175-202.

Tipton, I. C. (1974). Berkeley: The philosophy of immaterialism. Methuen.

Turbayne, C. M. (1955). Locke, Berkeley, and the doctrine of abstraction. Philosophical Review, 64(4), 515-528.